Foundationalism: in praise of vagueness

Thoughts inspired by teaching epistemology for the first time and listening to the podcasts of Jordan Peterson

Epistemology became a major topic for analytic philosophers because they trace their intellectual origins to Descartes and the British empiricists. Descartes dismantles the foundations of his beliefs and then tries to rebuild them on certain grounds. Having used the method of doubt to tear everything down, including even mathematics, he finds irrefutable evidence of the existence of his own mind and then tries to prove that the “external world” exists.

Descartes

René Descartes

The British empiricists take their inspiration from Descartes, accept his distinction between mind and body and plump for body as the truly real. Following Galileo and Montaigne’s distinction between primary and secondary qualities, they attempt to dispose of mind-related secondary qualities as merely “subjective” and thus nonexistent.

Strangely enough, analytic philosophers complacently flip between claiming that physical reality is the paradigm of the real and also thinking that the existence of the external world is questionable and in need of proof. It is the latter that drives the analytic philosopher’s interest in epistemology.

The schizophrenic result is that analytic philosophers accept the reality of their own minds and think that there is a need for a philosophical theory proving the entire physical universe outside their minds exists while also venerating Daniel Dennett, Paul Churchland and Francis Crick as philosophers eminently worthy of serious attention and respect though they argue for the unreality of mind.

When a student asked “what’s the external world?” in the Fall semester of 2017 the emperor’s new clothes naiveté of the question was most admirable and Plato’s comment in The Symposium “you’d never have heard what I’m going to tell you now if there wasn’t something in the proverb, ‘Drunkards and children tell the truth’ – drunkards anyway” (217e) came to mind. How nice never to have heard of the so-called external world!

Symposium

Analytic philosophers describe foundationalism as the notion that the accumulation of knowledge begins with certain foundations. The foundations are supposed to be certain because they are self-evident or indubitable in some other way. These foundations are the axioms upon which all other beliefs and knowledge then rest. This model is quasi-mathematical. Historically, most philosophers have adhered to some form of foundationalism.

The notion that knowledge simply accumulates and that one belief can be stacked upon

NPG x31082; G.E. Moore by Ramsey & Muspratt

G. E. Moore

another into an inviolable system, beginning with an axiom, with neat inferences from one belief to the next is naïve beyond belief. However, the truth of foundationalism is that at the core of someone’s general worldview, his basic stance towards reality, is some kind of metaphysical commitment and many if not all of his beliefs will reflect this basic commitment – depending on how consistent he is. Complicating matters is the fact that a person’s stated beliefs and his real beliefs often conflict. Someone’s real beliefs can be seen through his actions. If someone were to claim to be skeptical about the existence of time but make plans for next year’s vacation, or if someone were to question whether a chair exists but proceeds to unthinkingly sit on it anyway, or if G. E. Moore thinks “is this my hand?” is a meaningful question but withdraws his hand when a knife descends towards it, then the person is a liar, fraud and hypocrite.

To put it in Platonic terms, real knowledge seems to require a congruence of head and heart, Logos and Thumos. There needs to be an agreement between what a person claims to know and what he actually believes. A person with an irrational fear of flying “knows” that plane travel is safe, but does not actually believe it – hence, they do not really know it at all.

Platonic soul

Analytic philosophers are typically committed atheists and materialists; the exceptions proving the rule. Since they exist in the conformist atmosphere of academia and they can control who enters the profession and who does not, there can appear to be an amazing consensus of belief concerning these metaphysical positions to the point that metaphysics fell largely out of favor in the academy. Philosophy is the study of inherently controversial and non-definitively provable matters and so consensus effectively removes a topic from philosophical view.

Aristotle

Aristotle

From an outside perspective, it seems that foundationalism has fallen out of favor because it is no longer recognized that adherence to materialism involves a metaphysical decision. Materialism is considered to be the sign of sanity and a prerequisite for being taken seriously in the profession. The question of materialism’s truth is no longer “live.” Such philosophers resolutely refuse to be troubled by quantum physics. The latter is at odds with the stable, common-sense seeming nature of Newtonian physics. Materialists seem to feel comfortable with atoms and molecules but shy away from the subatomic realm with its very strange behavior and postulates. Things like quantum foam, the notion that atoms are mostly empty space, observation changing the behavior of photons in the double-slit experiment, Shrödinger’s Cat, and the idea that electrons can exist in an infinite number of places simultaneously, for instance, do not seem consistent with a complacent attitude towards the physical.

Foundationalism as conceived by analytic philosophers is categorically wrong and is in fact not a live option for any rational person. Two thousand five hundred years ago, Aristotle famously pointed out that first principles are not provable. First principles are axiomatic assumptions from which subsequent reasoning follows. These principles avoid an infinite regress where one belief is justified by another belief which is justified by a prior commitment, etc.. Simply stated, it is necessary to start somewhere.

Gödel’s Theorem proves that not only are axioms articles of faith to be treated as self-evident, but axiomatic systems also generate unprovable statements. There will be truths, Gödelian propositions, whose truth or falsity cannot be decided with reference to those axioms. No axiomatic system of any complexity can be both consistent and “complete;” with all true statements proved within the system. Everything can be proved only if inconsistencies (contradictions) are permitted, but that would mean “proving” even false propositions to be true. Therefore, the search for a set of axioms that can capture all knowledge; all true statements, will be fruitless. There is a question mark concerning the most basic and fundamental features of reality. There are no axioms that can account for all features of reality. Since humans need to live and act in the world, they must make their best guesses and then evaluate their guesses in light of the consequences. If their experiences conflict with their assumptions and particularly if life becomes intolerable or impossible as a result, then assumptions will need to be altered.

William James

William James

This seems to be humanity’s existential situation and it requires what William James called a leap of faith.

Modern alternatives to foundationalism, the latter mischaracterized as needing to rest on indubitable truths, have been proposed. One is “reliabilism.” This recent notion claims that to have a justified, true belief, the justification must rest on some reliable method for justifying belief. The reliable method can be either some global thing, under some conceptions, or the reliable method might be relative to whatever field of knowledge or endeavor a person is considering.

Reliabilism seems to suffer from being blandly trivial and also from being ridiculously simple-minded. If the question were to be “should someone use an unreliable method for gathering knowledge?” of course the answer is no. A reliable method should be chosen. So much for the trivial. But the notion that all my knowledge should be based on some reliable method for determining the truth seems to be the stuff of fantasy.  What reliable method is there for determining important life decisions or a person’s metaphysical commitments? And metaphysical commitments have a way of permeating many many important beliefs and ways of acting. Aristotle and Gödel have already established that acts of faith are required for moderately complex thought and they are certainly going to be required for action.

Reliabilism, without acknowledging the necessity of a starting point, is also going to suffer from infinite regresses – a reliable method will need to be found for proving that a reliable method has been found and a reliable method will be needed for that and so on.

Coherentism responds to this by suggesting that all knowledge is inferential and no beliefs have any special foundational position. One item of knowledge is inferred from the next. Infinite regresses are avoided by making one’s beliefs circular. A turtle is holding up the earth. What is holding up the turtle? Another turtle. What is holding that turtle up? Another turtle. But if someone just keeps saying “another turtle” nothing has been explained and there is an infinite regress. The coherentist solves this by saying that we know that the thirtieth turtle is holding up the earth because the first turtle is holding up the earth.

Unfortunately, there is no agreement about what “coherent” means. One idea is that if A Turtlesimplies B and B implies C and C implies A, than ABC are part of a coherent web of belief. But this seems too strict, for some beliefs are not going to be so neatly derivable. It seems like “coherent” should mean at least that beliefs should be consistent with each other in which case the call for coherence is just the call for consistency. Or coherence could be that one’s web of beliefs expresses some coherent vision or story of some kind with each belief implying the other. The problem then is that there might be two completely incommensurate coherentist belief systems and thus what is and is not “knowledge” could differ from person to person. The other problem is that there seems no room for reality and truth to impinge. A coherent system of inferential beliefs seems self-contained with no real grounds for remedy should things go wrong.

There is the additional implication that if experience, intuition, revelation, faith, or something similar cannot punch through the circle of inferential beliefs to some underlying reality, then the basis for coherentist systems is merely mimetic. The coherentist copies his ideas from someone else.

Coherentism seems to be wrong also because some beliefs do seem to have special foundational status – namely, they embody some particular metaphysical commitment or other. It is possible that though the theory is unsatisfactory, its name may imply the intuition that someone’s body of beliefs should generally make sense relative to one another. It would seem to be a very strange way to live to simply have a collection of random and unrelated “facts” within one’s ken about which no coherent story can be told. From what might perhaps be called a poetic or metaphorical point of view, the name “coherentism” would seem to imply that someone’s beliefs should perhaps loosely make sense relative to one another and express some moderately coherent worldview. Thus coherentism would collapse back into the version of foundationalism that I am defending. This, however, is speculative. But the speculation is supported by the fact that though coherentism has a certain popularity among some analytic philosophers, any attempt to be more precise about what it is for a belief system to be coherent has failed.

So one problem with coherentism is its unpinning from reality – caught in a circle of inference.

Jordan Peterson makes a suggestion that would illustrate one way to avoid theories with this implication. He comments that mental and physical pain tend to be experienced as real, unignorable and undeniable. Pain has a worldview and a vision of being.
Among other things, it divides the world into those things inducing pain, such as meaninglessness, and those which do not. They thus provide insight into the nature of being. This would seem to be moment when a reality of some kind could penetrate the circle of coherentism, again, returning us back to foundationalism.

Reliabilism and coherentism have not enjoyed the popularity of foundationalism and seem like dead ends. Neither notion has any particularly widespread acceptance or adherence.

Historically, at least, foundationalism remains the most popular epistemic position.

Dostoevsky

Fyodor Dostoevsky

Nearly everyone agrees that the Cartesian project of creating certain and indubitable foundations for knowledge failed. The Cogito (I am thinking therefore I am) has some plausibility, but Descartes found it singularly difficult to found anything much on this beginning point.

The question then arises, would it be good thing if Descartes or another philosopher actually succeeded in finding definitively true foundations for knowledge?

The answer is no. The quest for certainty is misguided and its attainment would be a catastrophic end of reality as we know it.

Dostoevsky examines the issue in Notes from Underground. His hero considers the possibility of a completed psychology and science in which every element of the human psyche and the objective world has been rendered intelligible and predictable. It turns out in this imaginary scenario, for instance, that everyone acts in his own self-interest and perhaps is driven by pleasure. The underground man writes that in order to regain his freedom, man would need to act to counter his self-interest and engage in complete perversity in order not to be a piano key pressed by the hand of Nature.

Imagine a “reliable method” for determining whom to marry. It would not be decided on the basis of love or respect, it would be purely rational. The question is plugged into the reliable method machine, and the reliable method machine spits out the answer and the answer is 100% reliably certain that this person, or actually anyone matching the same criteria, is the one for you. Instead of saying “I pledge my troth to thee” and in doing so I am taking a chance on you, our fates will be intertwined and for richer and for poorer, in sickness and in health, we will love and support each other, a person will obediently follow the dictates of the reliability machine.

A world of certainty would be intolerable and dead.

Marduk and Tiamat

Marduk (Hero) killing Tiamat (Chaos)

Myth and religion describe a universe of Chaos and Order. Order is painfully derived out of the cut up body of Chaos. Order is the Logos; the word that helps organize reality into manageable sections. It is masculine consciousness that emerges out of the feminine Chaos. The Great Mother both nurtures and succors, but also destroys and engulfs – the Oedipal mother who eats her offspring by not permitting independence of existence.

Chaos is the unknown, the unpredictable, the infinite, the destroyer, failure and pain. It is the source of the tragic aspect of life – a life that must be redeemed by living meaningfully. Pain and suffering are worth bearing if the goal is worthwhile and in fact pain and suffering will even be joyfully submitted to.

Chaos is also where creativity comes from. Science exists in the context of the unpredictable, the unknown and the uncontrollable. There is no need to seek to know if there is no unknown. The attempt to predict and control implies the existence of the unpredicted and the uncontrollable.

The hero bravely confronts Chaos and wrests something from it. We learn by assimilating what was unknown to us and what once defeated us. A parent learns patience when confronted with a baby and thus grows.

To learn a person must be prepared to be a fool – for we are all fools relative to what we do not know. Pride prevents learning – a most Platonic thought.

A good life walks the border between Order and Chaos. Order is the father, the patriarchy, the rule giver and the Logos. Order is structure and hierarchy. Too much order and the father becomes tyrannical and illegitimate. Life and society cannot function without this order which is always imperfect and dead, since it is the gift of the dead to the living. As such it will be imperfect and the young will inevitably notice these imperfections and chafe against them. To socialize a child it is necessary to say no which can be stultifying. It is necessary to give up spontaneous action and unguided will for mutual well-being and social life.

So a happy childhood will combine structure, which is provided externally by the child’s parents – regular meals, patterns of waking and sleeping – with relatively unrestricted play with other children that lets the imagination run free. Creativity and imagination explore the unknown. We learn by entering the unknown and making it familiar.

Too much Order and life is boring and stultifying. Creativity and imagination are lost and learning ceases.

Too much Chaos spells death and insanity. The social rules break down and neighbor murders neighbor, the dykes break, and the flood destroys all.

A perfected psychology, which fortunately is an impossibility, would render each one of us predictable and thus prove that we are all rule-governed devices, since only the mechanistic can be predicted. The underground man’s perversity would actually be common good sense because it would reintroduce Chaos and fecund creativity into a barren world of nothing but Order with no room for free play or growth.

A completed science and psychology would be a living hell making life an unbearable burden and rendering it meaningless. No more leaps of faith and no more mystery of being. No problems to solve. The reliability machine would render everything else machine-like.

Analytic philosophers consider a philosopher to be rigorous if vagueness and ambiguity is eliminated from his thinking. This irascible reaching for certainty and clarity is misguided, mischaracterizing reality as it does.  His goal, if reached, would make life intolerable.

Descartes’ certainty would be the death of the soul. First principles would no longer depend on an act of faith and thus would no longer be freely chosen. All rational people would be compelled to accept the same starting assumptions for life and reality – making rationality an abomination.

As Peterson says, historically the devil is hyper-rational. He is an ideologue who falls in love with the creations of his own mind removing from the picture what is above him and below him and imagining like the analytic philosopher that all being is waiting for him to prove it exists through the great epistemological theory – the one that will finally prove that he, the philosopher, is not alone, trapped in his own mind. Since all the rest of us are part of his “external world” we too must await the products of his philosophical imagination to see whether we actually exist or not.

Satan

Scientism ignores the context of scientific discovery which is Chaos, the unknown, the unpredictable and the uncertain by focusing on what is visible to it – the results of science which identifies the mechanistic elements of reality, the measurable and unobscured. Through this mistake, all that is invisible to science, is thought not to exist, which includes God, consciousness, morality, emotion, value, purpose and beauty.

Our ancestors had a technology for navigating between Chaos and Order that did justice to both. Myths are sophisticated attempts to describe the human existential situation and to offer suggestions about how to deal with the sorts of crises human experience. They have the advantage that rationality, that rare thing, is not a requirement for getting something of value from them. They are not bad history or bad science.

Plato’s character from the Symposium, his version of Aristophanes, tells a story about hubris and romantic love. God creates globular people with two faces and four arms and legs. Self-sufficient, they roll down hills by sticking out their arms and legs. Too strong for their own good, they hubristically challenge the gods. Ultimate hubris means arrogance in the face of infinite, the almighty, ultimate reality, and ignoring the limits of man’s abilities. These failings mean death. This is an important idea to remember and understand. Be appropriately respectful and even fearful in the face of the unknown and remember what you do not know and cannot do or an implacable force, personified by the gods, will strike you down.

Globular people

The people are lucky for Zeus decides to be merciful, and to restrain their hubris he cuts the globular people into two. This has the unfortunate effect that the two separated halves want nothing more than to cling to each other to be reunited into one. In their attempt to achieve unity, they hug until they die.

This implies that an excessive closeness and attempt to simply merge with another person is pathological. “Do not drink from the same cup” might capture this notion. You may care for the other person as for yourself, but it is necessary to respect the other person’s wishes and desires which will not always be identical to your own which necessitates a spirit of compromise.

Zeus takes pity on the people and invents sex which permits humans to engage in an ecstatic unity which temporarily slakes their thirsts for each other and permits them to get on with their lives, parting and then joining in a cycle.

This story captures many of the feelings and perhaps the essence of romantic love better than some scientific or rational analysis. If humans were to try to explain earthly romantic love to aliens unfamiliar with it, this story would be a good introduction.

The story of Adam and Eve likewise does a good job of describing the human condition. When after the Fall, it is said that women will face the danger of childbirth in pain and men will toil and sweat over the thorn-ridden earth and that both men and women will die – having arisen from the dust they will return to the dust – this is simply descriptively accurate. Having eaten from the tree of knowledge, we know both good and evil and thus have the burden of moral responsibility for our actions and we also know we will die, which makes us unique among God’s creatures.

Garden of Eden

The Garden of Eden containing such obvious symbolism as the Tree of Life and Tree of Knowledge, confirming that this is not supposed to be literal history, imagines an animal past where we were once innocent since we were without knowledge of right and wrong. We cannot return to that animal past for flaming swords symbolically prevent us. Erich Fromm in The Art of Loving comments that the human paradise is to be obtained through love and not by a retreat to animal-like innocence. Once right and wrong exist, they cannot be ignored without acquiring moral guilt.

The struggle to make sense of life and to have any worthwhile advice about how to make the most of it is a life-long endeavor. There is no certainty of foundations and no reliable method that can be counted on to produce the right results and correct guesses.

Foundationalism cannot rest on self-evident axioms. The most that can be achieved is to treat such axioms as self-evident and move on from there. To treat foundationalism as requiring truly certain axioms is to take Descartes as one’s paradigm instead of Plato and Aristotle. Cartesianism is rightly rejected since it would destroy life and human existence by introducing nothing but the known and the orderly. Even if it somehow made sense, it would still not make sense for individuals, since aspects of what is Chaos and what is Order are relative to the individual. A mastered aspect of life is Order and what is unknown remains Chaos and so narratives that make room for both would always be necessary to capture ontogenetic reality if not phylogenetic.

 

 

12 thoughts on “Foundationalism: in praise of vagueness

  1. Pingback: Foundationalism: in praise of vagueness | @the_arv

  2. Pingback: Foundationalism: in praise of vagueness | Reaction Times

  3. Pingback: Of Self-Evident Proofs… | The Deus Ex Machina Blog

  4. How can we be sure that a proposition is true?

    Take a simple example. Sometimes, when they can’t find something, one hears people say, “It can’t have simply vanished.” It is something they take for granted.

    But how do they know this? It is not a logical impossibility that things should simply vanish; we can quite easily imagine something just disappearing and re-appearing, like the Cheshire Cat in Alice in Wonderland.

    This suggests “things don’t simply vanish” is an empirical or scientific proposition, an hypothesis that needs to be tested. But there is an obvious difficulty here; accepting even the possibility of things “simply vanishing” has all sorts of implications for what would count as testing, proving, how we interpret evidence and our whole system of verification.

    The solution is simple enough: “things don’t simply vanish” is a rule, a practice, a regulative principle for the way we judge and act, from the most rigorous scientific enquires to the most ordinary everyday activities.

    This does not make it, as the sceptic claims, a groundless assertion. As Wittgenstein explains, “Regarding such statements as absolutely solid is part of our METHOD of doubt and enquiry.” He adds that “I do not explicitly learn the propositions that stand fast for me. I can discover them subsequently like the axis around which a body rotates. This axis is not fixed in the sense that anything holds it fast, but the movement around it determines its immobility.”

    “Cogito ergo sum” may or may not be self-evident; that it is composed of Latin words, whose meaning I understand most certainly is.

    • @Michael Paterson-Seymour – the degree and kind of certainty to which Wittgenstein refers is fine by me. I also taught “On Certainty” this semester and agree with it. I find the epistemic skepticism of analytic philosophers tiresome and boring because it is not motivated by any real doubt – just a pretend doubt where the question habit has gone wrong and the language-game is stuck. G.E. Moore and his analytic descendants never get beyond ‘is this my hand.’ They imagine that some theory is going to be more basic, trustworthy, than that experience.

      We are in agreement that much of what passes for epistemic skepticism is a pointless waste of time. The interesting questions center around the meaning of life, not hands existing, and such important questions do not admit of definitive answers that all rational people must agree to. We grope in the darkness and peer through the mists and do our best to come up with preliminary and tentative conclusions. And, most of all, need hope and faith.

      There is meaningful uncertainty and then pretend uncertainty belied by actions. “Things don’t simply vanish” is fine. It’s a sensible heuristic that as Karl Popper pointed out is not provable, only falsifiable. But, he thought, that is the nature of science. The only reason Popper mentions it is because he thinks only falsifiable scientific theories count as science at all. It’s not a reason for skepticism.

      In conclusion, bad foundationalism demands foundations that are of a kind of certainty that Wittgenstein rightly rejects as a misunderstanding of language games (perhaps he might say?). Good foundationalism admits that its most profound (deep, basic) axioms are not definitively provable in a way that excludes skepticism but then asks “So, what? It’s the nature of reality. Just ask Goedel.”

      I also agree with Heidegger that we are “being-in-the-world.” We find ourselves in the world already and then find ourselves trying to make sense of it and sometimes theorizing about it, but our being in the world is not itself the product of theory nor could it be. Philosophers like me are not the target of Wittgenstein’s sensible arguments. I agree with him. It’s the analytic-types who are wasting everyone’s time. We should be able to agree that “things don’t simply vanish” but “life and the universe is purposeful and the tragedy of life can be redeemed by living a good one” are acts of unprovable faith. As Goedel’s theorem implies, not all true things can be proven to be true.

      • “G.E. Moore and his analytic descendants never get beyond ‘is this my hand.”

        One recalls Wittgenstein’s retort in “On Certainty” (with which I, too, agree):

        “125. If a blind man were to ask me “Have you got two hands?” I should not make sure by looking. If I were to have any doubt of it, then I don’t know why I should trust my eyes. For why shouldn’t I test my eyes by looking to find out whether I see my two hands? What is to be tested by what? (Who decides what stands fast?)

        And what does it mean to say that such and such stands fast?”

      • @Michaeal Paterson-Seymour: That is the precise Wittgenstein quotation that has stuck in my mind for years and is often brought up in my lectures. It’s a great one.

  5. Vagueness is sometimes indicative of bad things such as senility or evasiveness, but it can also indicate intellectual humility. Of course intellectual and humility seldom belong in the same sentence, since of all man’s prides, intellectual pride may be the greatest. Our finest minds have been working for millennia to hide this fact and shift attention to, say, the pride some young women take in the gloss of their hair. And intellectual humility should lead to intellectual charity, although in my experience, what we usually find is mock intellectual humility learning to imperious strictures on an alleged lack of intellectual charity in others. Many agnostics take this line: “I know nothing and therefore know that nothing can be known.”

    Your description of “good foundationalism” seems to match what I think of as “good postmodernism,” which some writers call post-foundationalism. This last name strikes me as wrong, since my “good foundationalism/postmodernism” doesn’t dispense with foundations, only recognizes that these foundations rest on something of an altogether different nature. What I take to be “bad foundationalism” leads to the Rationalist thought prison that you so rightly warn against. I don’t know about you, but Rationalism (in Oakeshotts’ sense) is in my experience the least charitable philosophy on the planet. Maybe I should say the most humorless.

    I think a sense of humor normally accompanies your healthy vagueness. I mean this in the old sense of awareness that men come in various humors–some melancholy, some sanguine, etc.–and that all of their (and our) lofty cogitations are colored by their humors. I don’t think we should trust any philosopher who doesn’t regularly give vent to some good-natured chuckling over what he and others say. Not derisive and sneering laughter–good-natured chuckling over the curious things people (including himself) think and say.

    I first read your post last night, just before turning out the light, at which time my mind was vague in a bad way. Too vague to form an answer, in any case. But with the morning comes at least this degree of clarity: you are right to praise vagueness and warn against “the prison of things that are clear” (Henri de Lubac, The Drama of Atheistic Humanism (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1995; Paris: Spes, 1944), pp. 91.) I would only add some words on behalf of good-natured chuckling.

    • Yes. Plato’s sense of humor, for instance, is one of his many virtues. I have told my students that if they are not laughing when they read certain dialogues, they are not understanding it. Jung too praised humor. The pretend-Aristophanes story is both funny and profound at the same time, which is always a winning combination.

  6. Thank you for this essay.

    Our own view for a long time was close to Susan Haack’s position:

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Foundherentism

    This is a good metaphor:

    “Haack introduces the analogy of the crossword puzzle to serve as a way of understanding how there can be mutual support among beliefs (as there is mutual support among crossword entries) without vicious circularity. The analogy between the structure of evidence and the crossword puzzle helps with another problem too. The clues to a crossword are the analogue of a person’s experiential evidence, and the already-completed intersecting entries are the analogue of his reasons for a belief. She claims that her metaphor has proven particularly fruitful in her own work, and has been found useful by many readers, not only philosophers but also scientists, economists, legal scholars, etc.”

    However, we have modified our views after reading Hans Hermann Hoppe’s Economic Science and the Austrian Method.

    Mises, as Hoppe explains and defends, established an indubitable foundation for knowledge – the “action axiom” – which is a synthetic proposition but justified a priori.

    Before reading Hoppe, we thought that such a thing was impossible but after many years of wrestling with Hume and Kant we quickly grasped that Mises had pulled off something marvelous in philosophy.

    We say more about this here:

    https://imperialenergyblog.wordpress.com/2017/07/19/philosophy-praxeology-and-power-1/

    As for “first principles” Nicholas Rescher thinks that they come, not at the start, but at the end of inquiry, via a process of a dialectic and philosophical exfoliation.

    This is generally true, but after Mises there is at least one indubitable principle.

Comment

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Google photo

You are commenting using your Google account. Log Out /  Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.